Hair on Fire: Contesting Consciousnesses
Peter Schultz
In a
bureaucracy, those who are “running around with their hair on fire” always lose
the arguments because they are not being objective.
And yet
bureaucracies actually fuel the “hair on fire” phenomenon because they drive
people to such behavior in an attempt to transcend objectivity to reveal “real
reality.” People are driven to such “extreme” behavior, which is then, because
it is seen as extreme, rejected. This illustrates the power of bureaucracy or
of an objectified consciousness. Those who don’t buy into this consciousness
are seen as “extreme” or “mad” or insane, and they are marginalized, ala’ the “Airplane
4 crowd” in the Minneapolis FBI office in the run-up to 9/11.
So, the
dispute over the “20th hijacker” in Minnesota was actually a contest
between the consciousness of objectivity and another kind of consciousness. The
same contest was evident in the run-up to the 9/11 attacks generally. But the
dissenters aren’t aware of what’s going on, that they are in fact challenging “the
single vision” consciousness that characterizes an objectified world. And they
are not aware that there are alternatives to that single vision consciousness.
Novelists
and poets are more likely to be aware of what’s going on. In fiction, presenting
an alternative consciousness is common. Witness Vonnegut, Austen, Twain,
Greene, McCarthy, or O’Brien. For Twain, what of Tom and Huck, two alternative
consciousnesses? Or Merlin and the Connecticut Yankee? Austen in Emma,
the early Emma and the later Emma? And of course not only in Emma. Or
what about Twain’s Joan of Arc? Did Joan represent an alternative
consciousness? And both the Church’s condemnation of Joan and her sainthood
miss her meaning, the meaning of her consciousness, as both her condemnation
and her sainthood flatten her out, reduce her complexity to make her fit into the
single vision. In these authors and their works, we can catch glimpses of “contesting
consciousnesses.”
And perhaps
this is what Aristotle and Machiavelli were about. Aristotle and Machiavelli were
investigating what I’ll call “the political consciousness,” and looking for and
indicating, at least covertly, an alternative. In investigating the political
consciousness both Aristotle and Machiavelli engaged in irony and, hence, their
teachings are at times humorous and meant to be humorous. And regarding
Aristotle, I can hear Pascal and his argument that Aristotle thought reforming
politics was like trying to bring order into a madhouse, meaning political
consciousness is, in fact, madness. As Pascal wrote, there are people who think that being “king” and “queen” is something real. And Aristotle
is famous for having asserted, “Man is the political animal," meaning that human beings have embraced political consciousness and even treat it as natural. And, regarding Machiavelli, because he was
investigating human consciousness, it is misleading to call
Machiavelli the teacher of evil, even though in some sense this is correct. Machiavelli
was saying, I think, that the evil is there, it’s a fact, even the fact
of life, but if it is objectified via government, it could
serve to ameliorate the human condition. Objectified, evil is useful, even indispensable. Of course, it is easy to think of
Plato’s Republic as his investigation of the political consciousness,
presented ironically through Socrates, whose philosophical consciousness was
humorously characterized by Aristophanes in The Clouds. And what of Augustine
and his Confessions? Another investigation of human
consciousness, one kind that is uninformed by God and another that is informed
by God?
Defending
philosophy is defending a particular and even peculiar kind of consciousness, a
consciousness that is always in conflict with political consciousness. And
this helps make sense of Socrates and his investigations of politicians, poets,
and artisans in Athens to see what they knew. And it also helps understand the subversive
character of Socrates’ conclusion that the difference between himself and the Athenians
is that while both didn’t know the most important stuff, Socrates knew he didn’t
know that stuff, while the others thought they did. For what could be more
challenging to political consciousness than a recognition, a claim that we
humans do not and probably cannot know the most important things because, after
all, what all politicians claim, and what all societies take for granted, is
that they know the most important things. A consciousness of ignorance is, as it were, always subversive.
[I said recently that all
politicians should learn to say, “We’ll see!” Which is what Zen Buddhists say.]